Popular Posts

Wednesday, September 18, 2013

Simone de Beauvoir

Simone de Beauvoir

Introduction
            Simone de Beauvoir was a French writer, intellectual, existentialist philosopher, political activist, feminist, and social theorist. While she did not consider herself a philosopher, Beauvoir had a significant influence on both feminist existentialism and feminist theory. She wrote extensively on the theory of subjectivity and identity and Existentialism. She opined relationship must not be institutionalized. This met with the disapproval of many of her friends and relatives.
Life sketch
Simone-Lucie-Ernestine-Marie Bertrand de Beauvoir, commonly known as Simone de Beauvoir was born on 9 January 1908.  She was the eldest daughter of a respected bourgeois family. 
De Beauvoir was educated in private institutions and under the religious discretion of her mother. De Beauvoir declared herself an atheist while she was still an adolescent, later arguing that religion was only a method of avoiding truth. She committed herself early to a life of learning, studying, and writing. When de Beauvoir was 21 years old she went to live with her grandmother, and began to study philosophy at the Sorbonne.
Writings
Beauvoir wrote novels, essays, biographies, an autobiography, and monographs on philosophy, politics, and social issues. She is best known for her novels, including She Came to Stay and The Mandarins, as well as her 1949 treatise The Second Sex, a detailed analysis of women's oppression and a foundational tract of contemporary feminism.
Background
1.      Personal conditions:
Simone de Beauvoir was born in Paris, the elder daughter of Georges Bertrand de Beauvoir, a legal secretary who once aspired to be an actor, and Françoise (née) Brasseur, a wealthy banker’s daughter and devout Catholic. The family struggled to maintain their bourgeois status after losing much of their fortune shortly after World War I, and Françoise insisted that the two daughters be sent to a prestigious convent school. Beauvoir herself was deeply religious as a child, at one point intending to become a nun (priest) until she experienced a crisis of faith at age 14, after which she remained an atheist for the rest of her life.

2.      Impact of Sartre’s philosophy:
In 1929 de Beauvoir passed her aggregation in philosophy with a thesis on Leibniz. This same year, she met a group of students including Paul Nizan, Andre Hermaid, and Jean-Paul Sartre, one of the key figures in the philosophy of Existentialism. Sartre and de Beauvoir began their lifelong partnership, becoming best friends and intellectual equals. The pair ranked as the top two students of their graduating class. The influence of the two philosophers on each other's work is remarkable. Their relationship would become famous for the unique commitment they made to each other which involved the freedom to love other people and the practice of complete openness and honesty between them. They would never marry, although it was spoken of at one point, for de Beauvoir in particular felt strongly that their relationship must not be institutionalized. This met with the disapproval of many of her friends and relatives.

3.      Impact of Hegel: (Immanence x Transcendence)
Beauvoir refuted a few thoughts of Hegel especially the ones dealing with immanence. Immanence refers to philosophical and metaphysical theories of divine presence in which the divine is seen to be manifested in or encompassing the material world. It is often contrasted with theories of Transcendence, in which the divine is seen to be outside the material world. It is usually applied in monotheistic, pantheistic, pandeistic, or panentheistic faiths to suggest that the spiritual world permeates the mundane.

Second wave feminism:
French philosopher Simone de Beauvoir provided a Marxist solution and an existentialist view on many of the questions of feminism with the publication of Le DeuxièmeSexe (The Second Sex) in 1949. The book expressed feminists' sense of injustice. Second-wave feminism is a feminist movement beginning in the early 1960s and continuing to the present; as such, it coexists with third-wave feminism. Second wave feminism is largely concerned with issues of equality other than suffrage, such as ending discrimination.
            Second-wave feminists see women's cultural and political inequalities as inextricably linked and encourage women to understand aspects of their personal lives as deeply politicized and as reflecting sexist power structures. The feminist activist and author Carol Hanisch coined the slogan "The Personal is Political", which became synonymous with the second wave.
Political philosophy of Beauvoir:
1.      Advocacy of feminism through ‘The Second Sex’:
“One is not born, but rather becomes, a woman”
Simone de Beauvoir
            Revolutionary and incendiary, The Second Sex is one of the earliest attempts to confront human history from a feminist perspective.In The Second Sex, her most famous work, de Beauvoir sketches a kind of existential history of a woman’s life: a story of how a woman’s attitude towards her body and bodily functions changes over the years, and of how society influences this attitude. Here de Beauvoir raises the core question of female embodiment: Are the supposed disadvantages of the female body actual disadvantages which exist objectively in all societies, or are they merely judged to be disadvantages by our society? She answers this question by exploring case studies of the various stages of female life. In these case studies the female body is presented as both positive and negative, and women as both oppressed and free. A woman’s body is the site of this ambiguity, for she can use it as a vehicle for her freedom and feel oppressed by it. There is no essential truth of the matter: it depends upon the extent to which a woman sees herself as a free subject rather than as the object of society’s gaze.
It won de Beauvoir many admirers and just as many detractors. Today, many regard this massive and meticulously researched masterwork as not only as pillar of feminist thought but of twentieth-century philosophy in general.
v  What is a woman?
      In her book, Simone de Beauvoir begins by explaining how she has wanted to write a book about women. The problem she faces during this story is what the definition of women is, do women really exists, and what is a woman. She explores the different aspects of life as a woman.
      Sartre observed that whatever we perceive, including other people, is rendered as an ‘object’ to our gaze and is defined by us. De Beauvoir takes up this idea and applies it to men’s perception of women. The very concept of ‘woman’, de Beauvoir argues, is a male concept: woman is always ‘other’ because the male is the ‘seer’: he is the subject and she the object – the meaning of what it is to be a woman is given by men.
      De Beauvoir argues that it is not the biological condition of women per se that constitutes a handicap: it is how a woman construes this condition which renders it positive or negative. None of the uniquely female experiences – the development of female sex organs, menstruation, pregnancy, menopause – have a meaning in themselves; but in a hostile or oppressive society they can come to take on the meaning of being a burden and disadvantage, as women come to accept the meanings a patriarchal society accords them.
            De Beauvoir points out that pre-adolescent boys and girls are really not very different: they “have the same interests and the same pleasures” (The Second Sex, p295, Translation and Ed, H.M. Parshley, Vintage, 1997). If the initial psychological differences between young boys and girls are relatively trivial, what then causes them to become important? If one ‘becomes’ a woman, how does this ‘becoming’ happen?

v  The Flesh and the Feminine:

Stages in a woman’s life

As a girl: De Beauvoir argues that as a girl’s bodily development occurs, each new stage is experienced as traumatic and demarcates her more and more sharply from the opposite sex. As the girl’s body matures, society reacts in an increasingly hostile and threatening manner. De Beauvoir talks about the process of ‘becoming flesh’, which is the process whereby one comes to experience oneself as a sexual, bodily being exposed to another’s gaze. This does not have to be a bad thing; but unfortunately, young girls are often forced to become flesh against their will: “The young girl feels that her body is getting away from her… on the street men follow her with their eyes and comment on her anatomy. She would like to be invisible; it frightens her to become flesh and to show flesh” (p333).

A Growing Girl: There are many more such events in a growing girl’s life which reinforce the belief that it is bad luck to be born with a female body. The female body is such a nuisance, a pain, an embarrassment, a problem to deal with, ugly, awkward, and so on. Even if a girl tries to forget that she has a female body, society will soon remind her. De Beauvoir gives several examples of this: the mother who frequently criticizes her daughter ’s body and posture, thus making her feel self-conscious; the ‘man on the street’ who makes a sexual comment about a young girl’s body, making her feel ashamed; and a girl’s embarrassment as male relatives make jokes about her menstruation.

Situations in which young women can be comfortable: However, de Beauvoir also gives positive examples of having a female body. She shows us that there are situations in which young women can be comfortable in their bodies – indeed, not only comfortable, but joyous and proud. Consider a girl who enjoys walking in the fields and woods, feeling a profound connection to nature. She has a great sense of happiness and freedom in her body which she doesn’t feel in a social environment. In nature there are no males to gaze upon her; there are no mothers to criticize her. She no longer sees herself through others’ eyes, and thus is finally free to define her body for herself.

Sexual intercourse:    But she cannot escape to the natural world forever. As part of belonging to a patriarchal society she must eventually undergo a further traumatic event – initiation into sexual intercourse. Intercourse is physically more traumatic for girls because it involves penetration and usually some corresponding pain. Culturally it is more traumatic because girls are kept in a greater state of ignorance than boys, and are often ill-prepared for what is to come. Culturally too, there are certain techniques of sexual intercourse which predominate, which may not be ideal for female enjoyment and orgasm (for instance, man on top). De Beauvoir points out that girls’ sexual education tends to be mainly of the ‘romantic’ sort, which emphasizes the courtship period and the pleasure of gentle caresses, but never the penetration. Thus when sex finally happens, it seems a world away from the romantic fantasies a girl has grown up with. De Beauvoir dryly observes that for the shocked young woman “love assumes the aspect of a surgical operation” (p404).
            Ultimately, is it the biological penetration itself which causes the distress, or is it the culturally-engineered ignorance of young women? De Beauvoir thinks the biological facts need not be traumatic: the distress is due to a lack of generosity in the man’s sexual behavior, combined with the woman’s fear of being objectified before an aggressive sexual gaze. She suggests that the way to a more positive sexual experience for both genders is through each partner acting in ‘erotic generosity’ towards the other, rather than in selfish sensuality.
Experience of Pregnancy: The experiences of pregnancy are more positive, yet still an ambiguous one for women: it can be both an unfair invasion of her body and at the same time a wonderful enrichment. As a woman’s pregnancy develops, society tends to consider her less sexually attractive, as no longer sexually available. This means that she temporarily escapes man’s sexual gaze. This is a positive development for a woman, de Beauvoir argues, because “now she is no longer in service as a sexual object, but she is the incarnation of her species, she represents the promise of life, of eternity” (p518).

The aging woman: What about as a woman gets older? The aging woman is described by de Beauvoir as “intent on struggling against a misfortune that was mysteriously disfiguring and deforming her” (p595). This is a very negative description of the aging process. It evokes the tone of a cosmetics advert which pressures women to buy their products to struggle against time. Nevertheless, de Beauvoir’s description is an honest one. We know from her autobiographical writings that she really struggled to come to terms with her aging body: she liked clothes, was considered attractive, and felt upset when she thought she was losing her looks. Yet as a philosopher she was able to step back and see that this attitude was due to an inordinate value placed by society on such ephemeral assets. She had accepted society’s definition of her worth as her own definition.
            She does admit that as a woman persists through the oncoming of age, she may find herself in a more positive stage of life: “She can also permit herself defiance of fashion and of ‘what people will say’; she is freed from social obligations, dieting, and the care of her beauty” (p595). So although old age has many negative aspects, it can provide a kind of escape from society’s pressure. The desire to conform is lifted, and freedom increases. De Beauvoir’s point is that freedom needs space to move. In the case of female embodiment, there is often no room for women to really ‘see their bodies through their own gaze’, since the male gaze permeates everywhere.

v  Free Space

The intertwinedness of body and mind helps explain women’s oppression. Women do not choose to think about their bodies and bodily processes negatively; rather they are forced to do so as a result of being embedded in a hostile patriarchal society. On this view the body is not just the thing we can prod and poke, it is shaped by a plethora of perceptions: if we feel bad about it, it becomes a ‘bad thing’; if we feel good about it, it becomes a ‘good thing’. But the way we think about it is not a matter of free choice unless we live in a society which gives space for that freedom. What feminist philosophers like de Beauvoir aim to do is to open up a space for that freedom to flourish.

v  Transcendence:
            Simone de Beauvoir’s own account of how ‘civilization as a whole [has produced] this creature, intermediate between male and eunuch, which is described as feminine’ goes along these lines: from early times, men have appropriated those activities which allowed "transcendence", and they have allocated women to activities which did not allow it. Among early humans: men controlled tools, and hunting and risked their lives (in hunting and war) whilst women were tied to reproduction and the maintenance of children. Her argument is that this happened ‘naturally’ – based on biological characteristics – but became fixed; and of course once trapped in a role which in itself prevented ‘transcendence’ women were destined to stay in this role for centuries.
      She therefore compares women’s experience with that of children: their world is ‘given’, and they are not able to imagine another one.Broadening out beyond the question of male-female relationships, de Beauvoir analyses different stances taken by men in regard to the possibility of transcendence: she says that sometimes men can exist in a state of ‘infantilism’, allowing themselves to become ‘sub-men’ e.g. in a lynch-mob. Others are (too) ‘serious’ i.e. they accept their role and don’t question it – their enthusiasms are ‘things detached from themselves’. Another kind of person is (too) ‘passionate’ – they “take the object of their enthusiasms to have an absolute value” ignoring the ultimately subjective nature of their passions. In doing this they may trample on the subjectivity of others. A fully free person recognises each person’s subjectivity – “Only the freedom of others can keep each one of us from hardening in the absurdity of facticity”. “To will oneself free is also to will others free.”

2.      Existentialism
A 20th century philosophical movement emphasizing the uniqueness of each human existence in freely making its self-defining choices.
      Generally for existentialists, one is not born anything: everything we are is the result of our choices, as we build ourselves out of our own resources and those which society gives us. We don’t only create our own values, we create ourselves. Simone de Beauvoir, although an avowed life-long existentialist posits limits to this central existentialist idea of self-creation and self-definition, qualifying the absolute freedom Jean-Paul Sartre posited in Being and Nothingness. By contrast de Beauvoir presents an ambiguous picture of human freedom, in which women struggle against the apparent disadvantages of the female body.

Beauvoir on existentialism:
1.      The importance of this to de Beauvoir, in her examination of the relationship of woman to man, is that this relationship is traditionally one of dependence; and this also ‘easy’ in the sense that it avoids the risks associated with economic and personal freedom. It is also (some would add!) understandable, given the pressures that a male-dominated society exerts over women. When women do strive to liberate themselves, men will either try to make them get ‘back into the home’ or will grant them ‘equality in difference.’ 
2.      Simone de Beauvoir’s involvement with existentialism began in 1929 when she met Jean Paul Sartre at the Sorbonne — indeed; aside from Sartre she is the one writer who accepted the existentialist label with the most enthusiasm. Much of her early work was focused on ethical matters — her second book, for example, was The Ethics of Ambiguity.
3.      In this work, de Beauvoir attempted to create a system of existentialist ethics that were founded upon the Satrean notion of radical human freedom that was on the one hand open to all the possibilities the future held, and on the other hand was committed to taking responsibility for all of one’s chosen actions. For de Beauvoir, part of the problem with this is the fact that human life is characterized by an ambiguity created by the combination of both an inner and an outer life.
4.      A person’s inner life is based upon their consciousness and their awareness of their own freedom. A person’s outer life, on the other hand, is based upon their being material objects — objects which are limited in their freedom by other objects (which includes both people and society). De Beauvoir further emphasized the rejection of things like how a person identifies themselves with some fixed set of qualities or values, arguing instead that being open to the future entails being open to change, even changes in values.
5.      De Beauvoir’s feminism was based explicitly on existentialist concepts and terminology. In her famous work The Second Sex, she traced the historical pattern of male oppression of women through historical, literary, and even mythical sources. Her conclusion was that the current repression experienced by women was largely due to the idea that maleness was the norm while femaleness is somehow “other” and “different.”
6.      Existentialist themes are prominent in this work because de Beauvoir argued that part of the problem which women faced was that the male-dominated society created definitions of what it means to be a man or a woman, acting as though there were some fixed male and female natures. This attitude became self-regenerating because women were taught to accept their own marginalization, thus leading to feelings of self-alienation which are unique to women. This, in turn, allowed their oppression to progress in a manner fundamentally different from that experienced by other groups in society.
7.      True to her existentialist principles, de Beauvoir argued that women should reject this process of being made (in the image of traditional expectation) but should instead become (in the sense of finding their own path in life). She also argued that while legal rights and economic independence were necessary for women, they also weren’t sufficient conditions for real freedom — ultimately, women have to take matters into their own hands.

Simone de Beauvoir brightly brings up the reasoning that women are not just meant for doing one thing (being in the house). They are not just meant to be used for one thing because they have many talents. "But the significance of the verb to be must be rightly understood here; it is in bad faith to give it a static value when it really has the dynamic Hegelian sense of ‘to have become’. Yes, women on the whole are today inferior to men; that is, their situation affords them fewer possibilities". Men still try to fight off that they are the stronger species and women are just "a menace to their morality and their interests".
Even though women have been fought for their freedom rights, their rights to be equals, their rights to be considered a human being and given respect, are still going to be branded with the status of being "the other"

Conclusion
1.      The theory of Subjectivity and Identity:
            While de Beauvoir's comprehensive work raises many interesting issues, what concerns in this context is her development of a theory of subjectivity and identity. Her famous statement, that one is not born but rather becomes a woman, can be read in this way as arguing that there is no ontological subjectivity which is the exclusive domain or men or women. Instead, subjectivity can be granted or withheld by the society in which potential knowing subjects come to existential consciousness. The result, according to de Beauvoir, of women's lack of existential subjectivity...

Separation of Women from Femininity: One of de Beauvoir's most important contributions to 20th century feminist thought is the separation of "woman" (as a biological entity) from "femininity" (as a social construction). In her attempt to frame the debate as such in this she is not entirely successful, since in her section on biology she paints a very discouraging picture of women's alienation from their bodies; though she views female biology as an obstacle to be surmounted instead of a fixed destiny, the fact remains that women's bodies are constituted as such. Still, this sense of possibilities and the body as a "situation" rather than a "thing" represents as positive a view as can be imagined within a paradigm that depends on transcendence of the physical self. De Beauvoir also argues that biology cannot be understood outside of its social, economic, and psychological context, and that biology alone is insufficient to explain why women are constituted as the Other. She concludes that: "Woman is determined not by her hormones or by mysterious instincts, but by the manner in which her body and her relation to the world are modified through the action of others than herself." (734)

2.                 De Beauvoir rejects psychoanalysis as an explanatory framework for a number of reasons. First, she refuses to accept the notion of sexuality as a given, and argues that the psychoanalytic paradigm gives short shrift to female sexual subjectivity, casting it only as a passive, pre-determined. More importantly, she proposes that the psychoanalytic model imposes a normative determinism on women's sexual development, removing all possibility of conscious action. In the traditional psychonanalytic model which de Beauvoir cites, women are consistently alienated objects buffeted by the winds of contradictory and male-centred sexual desires, who can achieve no more than an ersatz morality which is an adherence to externally determined standards, not a result of a conscious attempt at transcendence and moral action.

3.       Rejects historical materialism:
           Though de Beauvoir attempts to build a historical model of women's subjugation, she rejects much of the historical materialism of theorists such as Engels. In her view, economic subjugation is insufficient to account for the existential Othering of women, and lacks theoretical complexity as an explanatory perspective. She states: "We must not believe, certainly, that a change in woman's economic condition alone is enough to transform her…" (734) Despite this rejection, she notes, in line with Marx, that it was "through labor that woman has conquered her dignity as a human being..."(144) and that "this [economic] factor has been and remains the basic factor in her evolution…" (734) Still, "until it has brought about the moral, social, cultural, and other consequences that it promises and requires, the new woman cannot appear."(734)

4.        Historical ethnography:
           Having largely discarded the theoretical streams of biology, psychoanalysis, and historical materialism, de Beauvoir turns her attention to historical ethnography as seen through an existentialist lens. This is, in my opinion, the weakest part of her argument. In effect, she creates a tautology and falls into the same theoretical trap that she previously critiques. She argues that men's activities within the context of prehistory both repeat and transcend life through invention and creation. Though she ostensibly rejects biology as an explanation for women's Otherization, she nevertheless locates existential immanence in early women's biological capacity to reproduce, stating that women's creative activities would have merely been regarded as reproducing life, rather than creating something new. She neither explains why women's childbearing capacity would only be seen as functional reiteration, nor what evidence exists that women did not themselves create, invent, or shape their physical world in the same way that men did. De Beauvoir's existentialist cast raises significant problems if we are to consider what role self-consciousness would have played in pre-modern humans. Of what significance would transcendence have been to people who were not using a post-Enlightenment conception of the individual, for example? Though she uses history as a theoretical tool, sheahistoricizes human behavior and existential capacities.

5.      Nature-culture binary De Beauvoir is theoretically indebted to the work of Levi-Strauss (of which Nancy Hartsock is critical), with its attendant problems, and situates women firmly in the familiar nature-culture binary. Women represent the chaotic ambivalence of nature, both idolized fertility and reviled uncontrolled sexuality, both life-bringer and destroyer. As de Beauvoir writes, "She is all that man desires and all that he does not attain." (229) Women represent the immanence of the flesh, both maternal and sexual. Women are symbolically All, which is to say nothing. Anticipating the work of the French feminists, de Beauvoir notes that women's mystery is derived in large part from the absence of language in which to understand them; metaphorically they exist in the realm of the pre-symbolic. As Other, women exist only in the way in which the One/Subject chooses to think of himself. In other words, women exist only as they are conceived of by men; they have no existence in their own right.
Also anticipating the work of postcolonial feminists, de Beauvoir draws parallels between women and colonized Others, noting that Others are situated within an unequal power dynamic: "[R]ich America, and the male, are on the master side and… Mystery belongs to the slave…The myth of woman is a luxury."(289) Again, the Other is held by the Subject to represent that which is chaotic and unknowable; to project undesirable qualities on to the Other is a luxury enjoyed by the epistemologically privileged. (Hill Collins, Hartsock, hooks, Harding)
De Beauvoir's model clearly privileges the epistemological position of the male. While it is perhaps unfair, given her historical context, to critique de Beauvoir for not thinking outside a Western binary model of male-female, particularly one which posits femaleness as a deficit and maleness as an epistemological standard, I feel this is a relevant point to be made from a theoretical standpoint. De Beauvoir's grounding in European existentialism, based in Cartesian dualism and in post-Enlightenment liberal notions of private property, does not account for other possible ways of seeing the world in terms of the relationship between self, other, and community. In assuming that all societies, for example, give primacy to private property in the same way, and moreover as the exclusive province of men, de Beauvoir creates an artificial social hierarchy that deems patrilineal, property-based societies to be the most existentially developed.
Another significant problem with de Beauvoir's theory is her use of evidence. For much of the book, she relies heavily on the literature and cultural products of the ancients to support her work. First, one can only imagine what conclusions could be drawn from examining the products of our cultural imagination out of their context. Second,
In the next section, de Beauvoir develops her famous truism about becoming a woman by tracing a general history of women's existential evolution from childhood to independent womanhood. Though she rejects psychoanalysis for the most part, apparently scorning the notion of penis envy, she still seems to be theoretically indebted to Freud for the basis of her speculations on childhood subjectivity. Of little boys, she writes: "Because he has an alter ego [a penis] in whom he sees himself, the little boy can boldly assume an attitude of subjectivity; the very object into which he projects himself becomes a symbol of autonomy, of transcendence, of power…" Of girls, de Beauvoir writes, "[She] cannot incarnate herself in any part of herself." (306) Thus, because of girls' physical "opaqueness" to themselves, they are unable to externalize their subjectivity sufficiently to develop existential autonomy. Here, it appears that de Beauvoir has either understood Freud too literally to realize that she has adopted much of his framework for childhood psychosexual development, or that she has anticipated the work of both the French feminists (particularly Luce Irigaray) and the neo-Freudians such as Nancy Chodorow. Subjectivity, for de Beauvoir, seems to begin located firmly in physical characteristics of boys and girls, even though she ostensibly rejects this notion outright. The boy, since he has a penis, projects his Self outward, in the idealized form of cognitive autonomy privileged by post-Enlightenment epistemologists, while the girl, since she has genitals that are "opaque", "hidden" and thus immanent. De Beauvoir argues that once children move beyond interest in excretory functions and their attendant meanings, it is social rewards attached to being male or female (physically and socially) that determine subjectivity.
Epistemologically, de Beauvoir anticipates the paradigm of "women's ways of knowing" of which Code is so critical. Again, she works with the nature-culture, female-male binary to argue that women's epistemological grounding is fundamentally different from men's by virtue of their biology and experience. This division between thinking/abstracting and living/experiencing is responsible, states de Beauvoir, for differences in male and female epistemologies and cognitive processes.

De Beauvoir's work is useful, not because of its theoretical framework, but rather for its singular significance as the first major 20th century work of liberal feminist thought. 

No comments:

Post a Comment